Friday, 8 May 2015
Classificatory disputes about what is art
Classificatory disputes about art
Art historians and philosophers of art have long had classificatory disputes about art regarding
whether a particular cultural form or piece of work should be classified as art. Disputes about
what does and does not count as art continue to occur today
Defining art is difficult if not impossible. Aestheticians and art philosophers often engage in
disputes about how to define art. By its original and broadest definition, art (from the Latin ars,
meaning "skill" or "craft") is the product or process of the effective application of a body of
knowledge, most often using a set of skills; this meaning is preserved in such phrases as
"liberal arts" and "martial arts". However, in the modern use of the word, which rose to
prominence after 1750, “art” is commonly understood to be skill used to produce an
aesthetic result (Hatcher, 1999).
Britannica Online defines it as "the use of skill and imagination in the creation of aesthetic
objects, environments, or experiences that can be shared with others". But how best to
define the term “art” today is a subject of much contention; many books and journal articles
have been published arguing over even the basics of what we mean by the term “art”
(Davies, 1991 and Carroll, 2000). Theodor Adorno claimed in 1969 “It is self-evident that
nothing concerning art is self-evident any more.” It is not clear who has the right to define
art. Artists, philosophers, anthropologists, and psychologists all use the notion of art in
their respective fields, and give it operational definitions that are not very similar to each
other's.
The second, more narrow, more recent sense of the word “art” is roughly as an abbreviation
for creative art or “fine art.”Here we mean that skill is being used to express the artist’s
creativity, or to engage the audience’s aesthetic sensibilities. Often, if the skill is being
used to create objects with a practical use, rather than paintings or sculpture with no
practical function other than as an artwork, it will be considered it as falling under
classifications such as the decorative arts, applied art and craft rather than fine art.
Likewise, if the skill is being used in a commercial or industrial way, it will be
considered design instead of art. Some thinkers have argued that the difference
between fine art and applied art has more to do with value judgments made about
the art than any clear definitional difference (Novitz, 1992). The modern distinction does
not work well for older periods, such as medieval art, where the most highly regarded
art media at the time were often metalwork, engraved gems, textiles and other
"applied arts", and the perceived value of artworks often reflected the cost of the
materials and sheer amount of time spent creating the work at least as much as the
creative input of the artist or artisan.
The traditional Western classifications since the Renaissance have been variants of the
hierarchy of genres based on the degree to which the work displays the imaginative input
of the artist, using artistic theory that goes back to the ancient world. Such thinking
received something of a boost with the aesthetics of Romanticism. A similar theoretical
framework applied in traditional Chinese art; for example in both the Western and Far
Eastern traditions of landscape painting (see literati painting), imaginary landscapes
were accorded a higher status than realistic depictions of an actual landscape view
- in the West relegated to "topographical views".
Many have argued that it is a mistake to even try to define art or beauty, that they
have no essence, and so can have no definition. Often, it is said that art is a cluster
of related concepts rather than a single concept. Examples of this approach include
Morris Weitz and Berys Gaut. Andy Warhol exhibited wooden sculptures of Brillo Boxes
as art.
Another approach is to say that “art” is basically a sociological category, that whatever
art schools and museums, and artists get away with is considered art regardless of formal
definitions. This institutional theory of art has been championed by George Dickie.
Most people did not consider a store-bought urinal or a sculptural depiction of a Brillo
Box to be art until Marcel Duchamp and Andy Warhol (respectively) placed them in the
context of art (i.e., the art gallery), which then provided the association of these objects
with the values that define art. For example when you bake bread in your kitchen it is
not considered as art, but do it in a gallery then it 'becomes art.' Undress or get dressed
at home it is not viewed as art, but do it in a gallery or as a 'performance' then it mighgt
be viewed as art. Cut up your clothes on your own it might not be interpreted as art, but
when Yoko Ono had others cut off pieces of her clothes in public it suddenly is viewed
as art, etc, etc.
Proceduralists often suggest that it is the process by which a work of art is created
or viewed that makes it, art, not any inherent feature of an object, or how wel
l received it is by the institutions of the art world after its introduction to society at
large. For John Dewey, for instance, if the writer intended a piece to be a poem,
it is one whether other poets acknowledge it or not. Whereas if exactly the same
set of words was written by a journalist, intending them as shorthand notes to help
him write a longer article later, these would not be a poem.
Leo Tolstoy, on the other hand, claims that what makes something art or not is how
it is experienced by its audience, not by the intention of its creator.Functionalists,
like Monroe Beardsley argue that whether a piece counts as art depends on what
function it plays in a particular context. For instance, the same Greek vase may play
a non-artistic function in one context (carrying wine), and an artistic function in
another context (helping us to appreciate the beauty of the human figure).
Philosopher David Novitz has argued that disagreements about the definition of art
are rarely the heart of the problem, rather that “the passionate concerns and interests
that humans vest in their social life” are “so much a part of all classificatory disputes
about art” (Novitz, 1996). According to Novitz, classificatory disputes are more often
disputes about our values and where we are trying to go with our society than they
are about theory proper. For example, when the Daily Mail criticized Damien Hirst
and Tracey Emin’s work by arguing "For 1,000 years art has been one of our great
civilising forces. Today, pickled sheep and soiled beds threaten to make barbarians
of us all" they are not advancing a definition or theory about art, but questioning
the value of Hirst’s and Emin’s work.
On the other hand, Thierry de Duve argues that disputes about the definition of art
are a necessary consequence of Marcel Duchamp's presentation of a readymade as
a work of art. In his 1996 book Kant After Duchamp he reinterprets Kant's Critique of
Judgement exchanging the phrase "this is beautiful" with "this is art", using Kantian
aesthetics to address post-Duchampian art.
The work of the French artist Marcel Duchamp from the 1910s and 1920s paved the
way for the conceptualists, providing them with examples of prototypically conceptua
l works (the readymades, for instance) that defied previous categorisations. Conceptua
l art emerged as a movement during the 1960s. The first wave of the "conceptual art"
movement extended from approximately 1967 to 1978. Early "concept" artists like
Henry Flynt, Robert Morris and Ray Johnson influenced the later, widely accepted
movement of conceptual artists like Dan Graham, Hans Haacke, and Douglas Huebler.
More recently, the “Young British Artists” (YBAs), led by Damien Hirst, came to
prominence in the 1990s and their work is seen as conceptual, even though it relies
very heavily on the art object to make its impact. The term is used in relation to them
on the basis that the object is not the artwork, or is often a found object, which has not
needed artistic skill in its production. Tracey Emin is seen as a leading YBA and a
conceptual artist, even though she has denied that she is and has emphasised
personal emotional expression.
Recent examples of disputed conceptual art
1991: Charles Saatchi funds Damien Hirst and the next year in the Saatchi Gallery
exhibits his The Physical Impossibility of Death in the Mind of Someone Living,
a shark in formaldehyde in a vitrine.
1993: Vanessa Beecroft holds her first performance in Milan, Italy, using young girls
to act as a second audience to the display of her diary of food.
1999: Tracey Emin is nominated for the Turner Prize. Part of her exhibit is My Bed,
her dishevelled bed, surrounded by detritus such as condoms, blood-stained
knickers, bottles and her bedroom slippers.
2001: Martin Creed wins the Turner Prize for The Lights Going On and Off, an
empty room where the lights go on and off.
2002: Miltos Manetas confronts the Whitney Biennial with his Whitneybiennial.com.
2005: Simon Starling wins the Turner Prize for Shedboatshed, a wooden shed which
he had turned into a boat, floated down the Rhine and turned back into a shed again.
The Stuckist group of artists, founded in 1999, proclaimed themselves "pro
-contemporary figurative painting with ideas and anti-conceptual art, mainly
because of its lack of concepts." They also called it pretentious, "unremarkable
and boring" and on July 25, 2002, in a demonstration, deposited a coffin outside
the White Cube gallery, marked "The Death of Conceptual Art".In 2003, the
Stuckism International Gallery exhibited a preserved shark under the title
A Dead Shark Isn't Art, clearly referencing the Damien Hirst work (see disputes above).
In 2002, Ivan Massow, the Chairman of the Institute of Contemporary Arts branded
conceptual art "pretentious, self-indulgent, craftless tat" and in "danger of
disappearing up its own arse ... led by cultural tsars such as the Tate's Sir
Nicholas Serota". Massow was consequently forced to resign. At the end of the
year, the Culture Minister, Kim Howells, an art school graduate, denounced
the Turner Prize as "cold, mechanical, conceptual bullshit".
In October 2004, the Saatchi Gallery told the media that "painting continues
to be the most relevant and vital way that artists choose to communicate."
Following this, Charles Saatchi began to sell prominent works from his YBA
(Young British Artists) collection.
Computer games date back as far as 1947, although they did not reach much
of an audience until the 1970s. It would be difficult and odd to deny that
computer and video games include many kinds of art (bearing in mind, of
course, that the concept "art" itself is, as indicated, open to a variety of
definitions). The graphics of a video game constitute digital art, graphic art,
and probably video art; the original soundtrack of a video game clearly constitutes
music. However it is a point of debate whether the video game as a whole should
be considered a piece of art of some kind, perhaps a form of interactive art.
Film critic Roger Ebert, for example, has gone on record claiming that video games
are not art, and for structural reasons will always be inferior to cinema, but then,
he admits his lack of knowledge in the area when he affirmed that he "will never
play a game when there is a good book to be read or a good movie to be watched."
Video game designer Hideo Kojima has argued that playing a videogame is not art,
but games do have artistic style and incorporate art.Video game designer Chris
Crawford argues that video games are art.[17] Esquire columnist Chuck Klosterman
also argues that video games are art.Tadhg Kelly argues that play itself is not art and
that fun is a constant required for all games so the art in games is the art of location
and place rather than interaction.
Subscribe to:
Post Comments (Atom)
No comments:
Post a Comment
Note: only a member of this blog may post a comment.